Semiotic Elucidation of the Emptiness View
claude.iconThis is a research paper by Gen Nakamura titled "A Semiotic Clarification of the Ku-kan". The main contents are as follows:.
2. by applying symbolic logic, it is shown that there are cases in which the logic of the middle-of-the-road school, traditionally considered illogical, is actually logically consistent.
3. by re-presenting arguments such as Tatsuki's "Middle Theory" in the form of symbolic logic formulas, we clarify the logical structure of these arguments.
4. he also attempts to interpret the unique logic of Buddhism, such as four-phrase discrimination, in terms of semiotics, but also points out that there are some aspects that cannot be fully explained. 5. raises the issue of whether "hollow" (śūnya) can be equated with the mathematical "zero" and is an issue for future work. 6. this study is a pioneering attempt to link Buddhist thought and modern logic, and suggests the possibility of a dialogue between the two.
The paper is an ambitious study that offers a new perspective on the comparative study of Buddhist and Western logic and attempts to shed light on the logical aspects of Buddhist thought.
Describing Buddhist logic in terms of symbolic logic rather than formal logic
From the standpoint of traditional logic, Indian logic appears to be asymmetric, but from the standpoint of symbolic logic, it is not asymmetric but rather traditional logic's adherence to useless rules.
Concepts are always genitive
This mountain has fire in it
There is fire here!
Fire is "here."
Indian logic
Here" is the subject.
traditional logic
Fire, here and there Inclusion Decision
There is fire here. Existence judgment
$ -a+b=1
$ a < b
The meaning of the former expression is that "everything is either a or b.
$ \neg A \vee B = \omega that
$ a-b=0
There can be nothing that is "a" and not "b".
$ A \wedge \neg B = \emptyset.
$ ab = a
a and what is b is a
$ A \wedge B = A.
These have no principalities.
I don't understand the usage of this symbol.nishio.icon
Understood! I added it.
I'm not sure whether to write it in a set style or logical formula style for a modern writing style.
https://gyazo.com/93828a1999d0cf14c0862c8bfa48e9e0
All a is b: $ a \subset b; ab = a; a - b = 0.
[$ A \subset B; A \cap B = A; A\cap\overline B=\emptyset.
So this is the same thing expressed in three different ways.
No a is b: $ a\subset -a; a-b= a; ab = 0.
$ a\subset -a??typo?nishio.icon
Opinion that AI is also a typo
$ a\subset -b.
[$ A \subset \overline B; A \cap \overline B = A; A\cap B=\emptyset.
Some a is b: $ a-b \neq a; ab\neq 0.
[$ A \cap \overline B \neq A; A\cap B \neq \emptyset.
Some a is not b: $ ab\neq a; a-b \neq 0.
[$ A \cap B \neq A; A\cap \overline B \neq \emptyset.
(formal) proposition
$ (x).\phi x.\subset (\exist x).\phi x
$ \phi a.\phi b.\phi c. \cdots\cdots: \subset \phi a \vee \phi b \vee \phi c \cdots\cdots.
Eh,$ \subsetがその位置にくるのこの記号の意味の意味は今の$ \subset ではなかったりする?nishio.icon
claude.iconThese equations will be expressed and explained in modern TeX.
$ (\forall x)\phi(x) \implies (\exists x)\phi(x)
Meaning: if φ(x) is true for all x, then φ(x) is true for at least one x.
$ \phi(a) \wedge \phi(b) \wedge \phi(c) \wedge \cdots \implies \phi(a) \vee \phi(b) \vee \phi(c) \vee \cdots
Meaning: φ(a), φ(b), φ(c), ... are all true, then φ(a) or φ(b) or φ(c) or ... is true.
Explanation: This shows a logical implication relation. It represents an inference from a conjunction (AND) to an election (OR). If all propositions are true, it means that at least one (in fact all) of them is true.
EIO $ ab=0.\quad bc\neq 0.\quad a-c\neq 0
$ A \cap B = \emptyset, \quad B \cap C \neq \emptyset, \quad A \cap \overline C \neq \emptyset
claude.iconEIO refers to three of the four propositional forms (A, E, I, O) used in traditional logic.
E: Full-symbol negation (No A is B)
I: Singular Affirmative (Some A is B)
O: Special-person negation (Some A is not B)
This formula expresses these three propositional forms in set-theoretic terms:
$ A \cap B = \emptysetNo intersection of A and B (E: No A is B)
$ B \cap C \neq \emptyset There is an intersection of B and C (I: Some B is C)
$ A \cap \overline C \neq \emptyset: Some A is not C (O: Some A is not C)
These formulas are a set-theoretic interpretation of the propositional forms of traditional logic, expressed in modern symbolic logic.
It is not illogical that the idiosyncratic judgment takes the form of an existence judgment.
https://gyazo.com/e5589df72fe9b322a79806aebff4700e
This is the story of "Japanese omits the subject! Japanese is ambiguous!" I believe that this is a counterargument to the Western view that "Japanese omits the subject!nishio.icon
That is, that people in languages that do not omit the subject are limited to certain thoughts by the constraints of the language and therefore cannot understand some of the conversations of people in languages that do omit the subject.
$ (\exist x).\phi(x).\equiv.\sim (x) . \sim \phi x
x for "people" and phi for "going to see cherry blossoms".
What do equiv and sim mean?nishio.icon
The one like sim is negative, equiv means equivalence as it is.
claude.icon$ (\exists x)\phi(x) \equiv \neg(\forall x)\neg\phi(x)
Meaning: "some x exists and φ(x) is true" is equivalent to the negation of "φ(x) is false for all x".
Commentary:.
$ (\exists x)\phi(x) uses the existential quantifier, which states that "some x exists and φ(x) is true".
$ \neg(\forall x)\neg\phi(x) uses the negation of the full symmetric quantifier.
$ (\forall x)\neg\phi(x) means "φ(x) is false for all x".
By negating its entirety, it means "φ(x) is not false for all x".
$ \equiv denotes logical equivalence.
This expression is one of the key theorems for quantifier duality. It expresses the relationship between existential and omnisymmetric quantifiers and shows that one can be defined by the other.
claude.icon
[Existence judgment: "A exists which is B."
They logically express the same content.
What has smoke is what has fire
Where there is smoke, there is fire.
In traditional logic, which was perfected in the Western Middle Ages following Aristotle, only the former was treated. The latter had to be rewritten in the form of a Priestly Affirmative Inclusion (A) like the former, or else in the form of a hypothetical inclusion.
claude.iconWe will explain this part using the notation of modern symbolic logic.
All symmetric affirmative decisions (A):$ (\forall x)(Sx \rightarrow Px)"All S are P"
Hypothetical decision:$ (\forall x)(Sx \rightarrow Px)"If x is S, then x is P"
Existence Decision: $ (\exists x)(Sx \wedge Px) "There exists x such that there is S and it is P."
Traditional logic since Aristotle dealt primarily with forms of the whole-person affirmative judgment (A). Existence judgments and judgments expressing special relations were often rewritten as either whole-person affirmative judgments or hypothetical judgments.
For example, the existence judgment "some S is P" could traditionally be rewritten as
As a full name positive judgment:
$ (\forall x)((Sx \wedge (\exists y)(Sy \wedge Py)) \rightarrow Px)
"For every x such that there exists an S which is S and which is P, x is P."
As a hypothetical judgment:
$ (\forall x)(Sx \rightarrow (\exists y)(Sy \wedge Py))
"If x is S, then there exists S such that P"
These rewrites were a way to get around the limitations of traditional logic, which cannot deal directly with existence judgments.
However, in modern symbolic logic, such complicated rewriting is no longer necessary because existence judgments can be expressed directly as $ (\exists x)(Sx \wedge Px).
https://gyazo.com/4578efb5d5dfa563667e5a74b05fbfa1
$ \psi\alpha
$ \phi\alpha
$ (x)\phi x . \supset \psi x .
$ \phi \alpha . \supset \psi \alpha.
$ (x).\phi x.\supset \psi x : \phi \alpha.\supset \psi \alpha
(Ratzel's theory of apparent variables)
this (something or someone close to the speaker (including the speaker), or ideas expressed by the speaker)$ (x)ってのは今で言うところの$ \forall xなのかなnishio.icon
Claude said it was.
However, in India, from these five items, instead of a three-stage argument, we proceeded to Russell's THEORY OF APPARENT VARIABLES
Here was also the usage at the time of $ \sim and $ \supset and so on
In the first place, is the whole nominal quantifier itself a relatively new concept around 1900?
https://gyazo.com/7bb8a086fff5645c8a3d8f6744f92a16
claude.iconTheory of apparent variables:.
This is a concept in logic proposed by Bertrand Russell, a theory that deals with variables bounded by quantifiers (∀ and ∃). The term "apparent variable" refers to a variable bounded by quantifiers.
Each equation in this text is written alongside the modern notation TeX to explain its meaning, andnishio.icon
claude.icon
Yes, we will gladly provide an explanation. I will explain the notation of symbolic logic used in this paper, along with the modern TeX notation and its meaning.
Aristotle's Deduction $ SaM. MaP.\supset SaP.
Modern TeX notation: $ (∀x)(Sx → Mx), (∀x)(Mx → Px) \vdash (∀x)(Sx → Px)
Meaning: All S is M. All M is P. Therefore, all S is P. (Trinitarianism)
I see what you mean.nishio.icon
Indian logic $ (x). \phi x \supset \psi x : \phi \alpha : \supset \psi \alpha
claude.iconModern TeX notation:
$ (\forall x)(\phi(x) \rightarrow \psi(x)) : \phi(\alpha) \rightarrow \psi(\alpha)
This expression can be interpreted as follows
$ (\forall x)(\phi(x) \rightarrow \psi(x)): For all x, if φ(x) then ψ(x)
$ \phi(\alpha): φ(α) holds for some particular α
$ \rightarrow \psi(\alpha): Then ψ(α) holds for that same α
In other words, this entire equation represents
There is a general rule that says that if φ(x) for all x, then ψ(x) holds, and if φ(α) holds for a particular α, then ψ(α) also holds for that α."
This formula expresses the application of a general rule (a totally symmetrically quantified proposition) to a specific case, and is an application of Russell's Theory of Apparent Variables. It shows the relationship between a totally symmetrically quantified x and a particular α. It illustrates the use of variables (x) and free variables (α) bounded by quantifiers.
Huh, I see. So you're saying that by using "apparent variables" we can express the three-stage argument this way.nishio.icon
The idea of using "apparent variables" that do not correspond to concrete things, which I used to use in programming and accepted without any sense of discomfort, was a "new mathematics" for Hajime Nakamura, which was created 40 years before this paper was written. Chapter 2
Theory of auspiciousness: $ \forall(x, y) xRy \rightarrow \neg(x = y) . \neg(x\neq y)
"Nothing can be x and non-x.
Pool: $ x(1-x)=x-x^2=x-x=0
Schröder: $ a(-a) = 0 = -aa
Logic of the time: $ \sim(p.\sim p)
Now expression: $ \neg(p \wedge \neg p)
According to Schröder's Logical Algebra, if a is a and nothing, then a is nothing.
$ a\times 0 = 0
Oh? What's that funny thing you just said?nishio.icon
Apart from what has already gone and what is yet to go, we do not recognize any other third kind of world path, namely, "what is now passing away.
$ a + -a = 1
No, I don't know about that.nishio.icon
I'm talking about how from this point on, the Dragon Tree Empty Argument is an Aristotelian method of reasoning that is NG, but from logical algebra, it's OK.
https://gyazo.com/c80f80f3ead929130881b59e81e34cb8
While the Saṅghya school adheres to the principle of the law of contradiction or the law of exhaustion, Buddhism tolerates a different kind of thought.
After criticizing you for equating sky with 0 in logical algebra because the original word for sky means zero, which is groundless, I give my reasons why I think sky is a good place to start.
But even then, not all of the empty arguments can be expressed by logic algebra, so I'm done talking about how logic may need to be extended - I'm not sure.
---
This page is auto-translated from /nishio/空観の記号論理学的解明 using DeepL. If you looks something interesting but the auto-translated English is not good enough to understand it, feel free to let me know at @nishio_en. I'm very happy to spread my thought to non-Japanese readers.